The Life and Times of Mencius
Mencius (Mengzi), born Meng Ke, hailed from the state of Zou during China’s Warring States period (475-221 BCE). Traditional accounts suggest he studied under disciples of Zisi, Confucius’ grandson, though modern scholars debate this lineage. The Ming dynasty’s “Genealogy of Mencius” records his birth on the second day of the fourth month in the fourth year of King Lie of Zhou’s reign (372 BCE) and his death on the fifteenth day of the eleventh month in the twenty-sixth year of King Nan’s reign (289 BCE), making him 84 years old at death. While these dates remain uncertain, they align with key events in Mencius’ life.
Historical records indicate Mencius visited King Hui of Liang when the ruler was in his later years, likely around the fifteenth year of King Hui’s reign. The famous account in the “Records of the Grand Historian” placing this meeting in King Hui’s thirty-fifth year appears unreliable. If Mencius was indeed born in 372 BCE, he would have been in his fifties during this audience, explaining why King Hui addressed him as “elderly sir.” The dating of his death proves more problematic, though the “Genealogy” account placing it around 289 BCE seems plausible if we accept that the “Book of Mencius” references events after Duke Ping of Lu’s death (296 BCE).
The Debate on Human Nature in Warring States China
Mencius entered a philosophical landscape already engaged in vigorous debate about human nature. The “Gaozi” chapter of the “Book of Mencius” preserves competing theories:
Gaozi argued that “human nature is neither good nor bad,” while others maintained that “human nature can become good or bad depending on circumstances,” citing how people followed virtuous rulers like Kings Wen and Wu but became violent under tyrants like Kings You and Li. A third position held that “some natures are good, some bad,” noting that even under sage rulers like Yao there were villains like Xiang.
Mencius synthesized these views into his famous theory of innate goodness, declaring:
“If we consider people’s innate capacities (qing), they can become good. This is what I mean by human nature being good. As for becoming bad, this is not the fault of their innate capacities.”
He identified four universal moral sprouts present in all humans:
1. Compassion – the sprout of benevolence (ren)
2. Shame – the sprout of righteousness (yi)
3. Courtesy – the sprout of propriety (li)
4. Sense of right/wrong – the sprout of wisdom (zhi)
These moral potentials, Mencius argued, distinguish humans from animals and form the foundation for ethical development.
The Structure of Mencius’ Ethical Theory
Mencius built his case for innate goodness through three interconnected arguments about human nature:
First, he observed universal human capacities. Just as all people share similar sensory experiences (enjoying the same flavors, appreciating the same music), they also share fundamental moral intuitions. The sage simply recognizes and cultivates these universal tendencies earlier than others.
Second, he identified the “four sprouts” – innate moral predispositions that spontaneously manifest in situations like seeing a child about to fall into a well. These reactions occur without calculation of benefit, proving their natural origin.
Third, he described “innate knowing and ability” (liangzhi liangneng) – moral knowledge and capacity requiring neither education nor reflection. The child’s natural love for parents and respect for elders demonstrates this innate moral orientation.
Explaining Moral Failure in a Good Nature
If human nature is fundamentally good, how does Mencius account for evil? He proposed three mechanisms:
1. Environmental corruption: Like water forced uphill against its nature, people can be distorted by adverse circumstances. Poor harvests might make youth violent, just as rich years make them lazy – not because their nature differs, but because conditions “drown” their moral sprouts.
2. Self-abandonment: Those who reject their moral potential become like deforested mountains – their “night qi” (moral vitality) cannot regenerate. Mencius warned against “self-violence” (rejecting ritual propriety) and “self-abandonment” (refusing to cultivate virtue).
3. Misguided cultivation: Prioritizing bodily appetites over moral development makes one “nourish the small parts” at the expense of the greater. The mind’s unique capacity for reflection should guide lesser faculties, not vice versa.
The Revolutionary Implications of Mencian Thought
Mencius’ philosophy carried profound social and political implications that distinguished him from earlier Confucians:
1. Radical equality: “Sages are of the same kind as us,” Mencius declared, establishing the theoretical basis for universal human dignity. His famous statement that “every man can become a Yao or Shun” implied moral potential transcends social status.
2. Political philosophy: His “people-centered” view (“The people are most important, the state next, the ruler least”) challenged authoritarianism. The right to revolt against tyrants (“regard the ruler as an enemy”) flowed logically from his moral vision.
3. Educational theory: Rejecting coercive methods, Mencius advocated “timely nurturing” like rain nourishing sprouts. Education meant drawing out innate capacities through proper models (like the archer’s target), not imposing external standards.
Mencius’ Enduring Legacy
The tension between Mencius’ idealism and practical governance continues to resonate. His “motherly policy” emphasizing people’s welfare contrasted with Confucius’ “fatherly” focus on moral rectification. While advocating benevolent rule, he maintained strict opposition to utilitarian ethics that privileged profit over righteousness.
Modern readers might critique his neglect of institutional checks on power or his optimistic view of human nature. Yet his vision of universal moral potential and government responsibility to the people’s welfare remains foundational to East Asian political thought. The “Mencian moment” in Chinese philosophy – affirming both human dignity and social responsibility – continues to inspire ethical reflection today.
Mencius transformed Confucianism from a ritual-centered tradition into a comprehensive moral and political philosophy. His synthesis of innate goodness, self-cultivation, and humane governance created an enduring framework for understanding the relationship between individual ethics and social flourishing. As contemporary societies grapple with questions of human nature and good governance, Mencius’ insights remain remarkably relevant.
No comments yet.